Sunday 18 September 2016

A Philosophy of the Environment

Posted by Thomas Scarborough
In spite of its crucial importance today, in practice we have little operational guidance for defining policies, strategies, and outcome targets with respect to the natural environment. Above all, there are no agreed philosophical grounds for its preservation. Reactions to its destruction are fragmentary.
In times past, it was possible for every individual, or every family group, to be self-sustaining through all the cycles of nature. Today, we have advanced beyond all possibility of such a lifestyle, although pockets of our planet retain such ways of life. Today, the whole of nature needs to sustain the whole of humankind. This requires more than a parochial approach to the environment. It requires a global environmental ethics, and global environmental principles.

There is a pressing need today for a rational basis for a healthy, balanced relationship with the natural environment – for 'a broadly-based philosophy', in the words of the Scottish theologian and philosopher John MacQuarrie. While one cannot underestimate the effectiveness of reactive measures to protect or to heal the environment – on all levels, individual, organisational, and governmental – the philosophical underpinnings are sorely missed. Any substantial philosophy today should be able to present definitive criteria for dealing with the environment.

Various 'base principles' have been suggested:
• that nature enjoys a sacred status,
• that every life form has a special goal,
• that the natural environment is vital to our human flourishing,
• that it is essential for our economic progress.
Yet beyond all such considerations, it may be the very complexity of nature which promises a solution.

There is something which sets the environment apart, which requires a different treatment to all other ethical issues. There is no system (insofar as we may speak of a system at all) which is more complex than our natural environment. The environment presents us with an infinity of relations. We would need a mind (or a computer) larger than nature itself to understand it. We may say therefore that it is 'beyond the condition of things'. It is beyond reducing, controlling, or bringing into the condition of things. It is unconditional.

The natural environment is the ultimate zone, in which a vast tissue of influences cannot be reduced. It is so much more than a sphere which merely should be 'protected'. It is sacred. It is tabu. A reductionistic approach to nature does not apply.

Not only this. For want of a concept as to how nature ought to be – since we cannot possibly possess such knowledge – we cannot say that it should be this way or that. 'Is' and 'ought' vanish here. It is in a sacred space even beyond the realm of ethics. With respect to nature, we cannot give and we cannot take, we can only receive. In fact nature stands as a vast and all-encompassing symbol to teach us the limitations of human reason.

On the basis of a belief in a sacred environment there is a principled way forward. The environment – both animate and inanimate – is not merely an object of wonder and awe, nor is it sentimentally sacred. Its sacredness is of biblical proportions: a sacredness which means that it stands under 'the ban'. Whatever the value of nature may be – whatever its stores, whatever its appeal – it must not be touched. The only way forward is to treat it on the basis that it is both off-limits and hands-off, and this is unconditional. It is non-negotiable.

Our own simple, built environment is of course ensconced in the natural environment. Of necessity, we disturb the environment, because we are a part of it. How then should it be possible for nature to be off-limits today, in our (post) modern world?

The notion of such separation is not merely a wistful one. There are large areas today which we do keep off-limits: contaminated areas, for instance, military zones, and diamond areas. These are as good as sacrosanct – and yet the environment seems by comparison to be treated with ambivalence. In fact in times past, the natural environment was indeed thought to be sacred – in some cases more valuable than the life of one who desecrated it.

Just a hundred years ago, nature did not need any assistance from humanity. That is, in our very recent past, we knew a world in which nature was allowed to be nature, and did not need human cosseting or monitoring. The deliberate, nation-wide, even global protection of the natural environment through human custodians is a comparatively recent development.

In short, a separation between the natural and the built environments should be – and has to be – a realistic goal. This goal will be achieved when the equilibrium of the environment is maintained in every part without human intervention – or rather, its dynamic equilibrium is maintained over all its various cycles. Since, however, nature is beyond the condition of things, this must be a self-sustaining dynamic equilibrium, without the influence of human custodians.
'Our immediate environment is not nature as formerly, but organisation. But this immunity from nature produces a new crop of dangers, which is the very organisation.' —Dietrich Bonhoeffer.

3 comments:

  1. Thank you, Thomas, for this. I was just reading a book (not the first, one meight say) which identified concern for the environment as a kind of game changer - gestalt shift thingy (when your perception suddenly changes). That said, I row back against the idea that nature used to be 'natural' ("Just a hundred years ago, nature did not need any assistance from humanity") - or that we now control nature - which is it fair todetect as themes here?

    ReplyDelete
  2. The big question Tessa is how we may have some kind of certainty as to how to deal with nature, but it seems to me that we are not finding it. This is an oft expressed concern today -- some say one of the biggest problems of our time. So this is an attempt to find some kind of definitive answer: on what 'rational basis' can we approach nature? Broadly speaking, I propose that the natural environment should be completely separated from the built environment. We cannot afford to do anything else, and the reasons are in my post. But one can press this too far I think, and lose the big picture. The 'built environment' is a vague term perhaps, but broadly I mean a 'human product'. This human product could include tracts of nature -- but there must be a nature besides, which is left alone.

    ReplyDelete
  3. A philosophy of the environment. Gregory Kyle Klug I think identifies the major options we have if we drive them to their 'pure expressions': (a) separate ourselves from the natural environment, or (b) find a way to integrate the natural environment with the built environment. Perhaps one could add (c): put it all out of our minds, it will self-adjust, even if this should mean our own extinction.

    Various people have thought the preservation of the environment to be a problem of epistemology. That is, how shall we know what to do? This applies very much to option (b) above, and less so to option (a). Option (b) in particular assumes that we are capable of knowing what to do -- and not only of knowing, but of acting on such knowledge. I am basically saying that we are incapable of knowing what to do, for the reason that the natural environment is infinitely complex. It is an in-principle problem. To aspire to 'managing the Earth closely', as Büscher and Fletcher ('Wilson is wrong') describe option (b), is I think arrogant. This then turns us to option (a), which itself is not clear cut, but I think a far surer option.

    One may say that the natural and the built environments co-existed successfully in the past, which is option (b). But in the past, people held tabus with regard to the environment, while today we are reduced to a profusion of reactive measures. This returns us to the question of epistemology. How shall we know what to do? We don't know, and we can't know, in principle. So we need to resign from management, and let it be.

    ReplyDelete

Recent Comments